Difference between revisions of "Dedekind domain"
m (I think an integral domain is usually defined to be commutative) |
(Invertibility of ideals) |
||
Line 10: | Line 10: | ||
* Dedekind domains have unique prime factorizations of [[ideal]]s (but not necessarily of elements). | * Dedekind domains have unique prime factorizations of [[ideal]]s (but not necessarily of elements). | ||
− | + | ||
There are also various properties of [[homological algebra|homological]] importance that Dedekind domains satisfy. | There are also various properties of [[homological algebra|homological]] importance that Dedekind domains satisfy. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ==Invertibility of Ideals== | ||
+ | Let <math>R</math> be a Dedekind domain with field of fractions <math>K</math>, and let <math>I</math> be any nonzero [[fractional ideal]] of <math>R</math>. We call <math>I</math> '''invertible''' if there is a fractional ideal <math>I^{-1}</math> such that <math>II^{-1}=R</math>. We shall show that all fractional ideals of <math>R</math> are invertible. | ||
+ | |||
+ | Given any nonzero fractional ideal <math>I</math> of <math>R</math> define <math>I^{-1} = \{\beta\in K|\beta I\subseteq R\}</math>. <math>I^{-1}</math> is clearly an <math>R</math>-[[module]]. Moreover, for any nonzero <math>\alpha \in I\cap R</math> (such an alpha clearly exists, if <math>x/y\in I</math> for <math>x,y\in R</math> then <math>x\in I</math>) we have <math>\alpha I^{-1}\subseteq R</math> by the definition of <math>I^{-1}</math>, and so <math>I^{-1}</math> must be a fractional ideal of <math>R</math>. It follows that <math>II^{-1}</math> is a fractional ideal of <math>R</math> as well, let <math>II^{-1} = A</math>. By definition, <math>A\subseteq R</math>, and so <math>A</math> is an integral ideal. We claim that in fact <math>A = R</math>, and so <math>I</math> is invertible. | ||
+ | |||
+ | We will need the following lemmas. | ||
+ | |||
+ | '''Lemma 1:''' Every nonzero integral ideal <math>J</math> of <math>R</math> contains a product of [[prime ideal]]s (counting <math>R</math> as the empty product). | ||
+ | |||
+ | ''Proof:'' Assume that this is not the case. Let <math>\mathcal S</math> be the collection of integral ideals of <math>R</math> not containing a product of prime ideals, so <math>\mathcal S</math> is nonempty and <math>R\not\in \mathcal S</math>. As <math>R</math> is noetherian, <math>\mathcal S</math> must have a maximal element, say <math>M</math>. Clearly <math>M</math> cannot be prime (otherwise it would contain itself), so there must be <math>x,y\in R</math> with <math>xy\in M</math> but <math>x,y\not\in M</math>. But then <math>M\subsetneq M+(x),M+(y)</math>, and so <math>M+(x)</math> and <math>M+(y)</math> contain products of prime ideals. But then <math>(M+(x))(M+(y)) = M+(xy)\subseteq M</math> also contains a product of prime ideals, contradicting the choice of <math>M</math>. <math>\square</math> | ||
+ | |||
+ | '''Lemma 2:''' For any proper integral ideal <math>J</math>, there is some <math>\gamma\in K\sm R</math> for which <math>\gamma J\subseteq R</math>. | ||
+ | |||
+ | ''Proof:'' Take any nonzero <math>a\in J</math>. By Lemma 1, <math>(a)</math> contains a product of prime ideals, say <math>(a)\supseteq P_1P_2\cdots P_n</math> with <math>n</math> minimal (i.e. <math>J</math> does not contain a product of <math>n-1</math> prime ideals). As <math>R\not\subseteq (a)</math>, <math>n\ge 1</math>. As <math>J</math> is a proper ideal, it must be contained in some maximal ideal, <math>P</math>. Since maximal ideals are prime in commutative rings, <math>P</math> is prime. But now <math>P_1P_2\cdots P_n\subseteq P</math>. Thus as <math>P</math> is prime, <math>P_i\subseteq P</math> for some <math>i</math> (if <math>P</math> is prime and <math>A,B</math> are ideals with <math>AB\subseteq P</math> then either <math>A\subseteq P</math> or <math>B\subseteq P</math>). But as <math>R</math> is a Dedekind domain, <math>P_i</math> must be maximal, so <math>P = P_i</math>. Now assume WLOG that <math>i = n</math>. By the minimality of <math>n</math>, <math>(P_1\cdots P_{n-1})\not\subseteq (a)</math>. Take any <math>b\in P_1\cdots P_{n-1}\sm (a)</math> let <math>\gamma = b/a\in K</math>. We claim that this is the desired <math>\gamma</math>. | ||
+ | |||
+ | First if <math>\gamma\in R</math> then <math>b = \gamma a\in (a)</math>, a contradiction, so <math>\gamma\not\in R</math>. Now for any <math>x\in J</math>, <math>bx\in P_1\cdots P_{n-1}J\subseteq P_1\cdots P_n\subseteq (a)</math>, and so <math>bx = ar</math> for some <math>r\in R</math>. But now <math>\gamma x = \frac{bx}{a} = r\in R</math>, and so <math>\gamma J\subseteq R</math>, as required. <math>\square</math> | ||
+ | |||
+ | Now we return to the main proof. Assume that <math>A\ne R</math>. Then by Lemma 2, there is some <math>\gamma\in K\sm R</math> for which <math>\gamma A\subseteq R</math>. By the definition of <math>I^{-1}</math>, for any <math>\beta\in I^{-1}</math> we have | ||
+ | <cmath>(\gamma\beta)I = \gamma(\beta I) \subseteq \gamma II^{-1} = \gamma A \subseteq R,</cmath> | ||
+ | and so <math>\gamma\beta\in I^{-1}</math>. It follows that <math>\gamma I^{-1}\subseteq I^{-1}</math>. We claim that this implies <math>\gamma\in R</math> (contradicting the choice of <math>\gamma</math>). | ||
+ | |||
+ | Indeed, the map <math>f:x\mapsto \gamma x</math> is an <math>R</math>-linear map from <math>I^{-1}\to I^{-1}</math>. As <math>R</math> is noetherian, <math>I^{-1}</math> must be a finitely generated <math>R</math>-module. Indeed, for some nonzero <math>r\in R</math>, <math>rI^{-1}</math> must be an integral ideal of <math>R</math>, which is finitely generated by the definition of noetherian rings. But if <math>rI^{-1} = Ry_1+\cdots + Ry_m</math> then <math>I^{-1} = R(y_1/r)+\cdots+R(y_m/r)</math>, so <math>I^{-1}</math> is finitely generated as well. Now take <math>I^{-1} = Rx_1+\cdots +Rx_m</math>, and let <math>M_f</math> be the [[matrix]] representation of <math>f</math> with respect to <math>x_1,\ldots,x_m</math>. Then <math>M_f</math> is an <math>m\times m</math> matrix with coefficients in <math>R</math> and we have: | ||
+ | <cmath>M_f | ||
+ | \left( | ||
+ | \begin{array}{c} | ||
+ | x_1\\ | ||
+ | x_2\\ | ||
+ | \vdots\\ | ||
+ | x_m | ||
+ | \end{array} | ||
+ | \right) | ||
+ | = | ||
+ | \gamma | ||
+ | \left( | ||
+ | \begin{array}{c} | ||
+ | x_1\\ | ||
+ | x_2\\ | ||
+ | \vdots\\ | ||
+ | x_m | ||
+ | \end{array} | ||
+ | \right), | ||
+ | </cmath> | ||
+ | and so <math>\gamma</math> is an [[eigenvalue]] of <math>M_f</math>. But then <math>\gamma</math> is a root of the [[characteristic polynomial]], <math>g(t) = |I_m(t)-M|</math> of <math>M_f</math>. But as <math>M_f</math> has all of its entries in <math>R</math>, <math>g(x)</math> is a monic polynomial in <math>R[x]</math>. Thus as <math>R</math> is integrally closed in <math>K</math>, <math>\gamma\in R</math>. | ||
+ | |||
+ | This is a contradiction, and so we must have <math>A = II^{-1} = R</math>, and so <math>I</math> is indeed invertible. <math>\blacksquare</math> | ||
+ | |||
+ | In fact, the converse is true as well: if all nonzero ideals are invertible, then <math>R</math> is a Dedekind domain. This is sometimes used as a definition of Dedekind domains. | ||
[[Category:Definition]] | [[Category:Definition]] | ||
[[Category:Ring theory]] | [[Category:Ring theory]] | ||
+ | [[Category:Algebraic number theory]] |
Revision as of 23:58, 28 November 2010
A Dedekind domain is a integral domain satisfying the following properties:
- is a noetherian ring.
- Every prime ideal of is a maximal ideal.
- is integrally closed in its field of fractions.
Dedekind domains are very important in abstract algebra and number theory. For example, the ring of integers of any number field is a Dedekind domain.
There are several very nice properties of Dedekind domains:
- Dedekind domains have unique prime factorizations of ideals (but not necessarily of elements).
There are also various properties of homological importance that Dedekind domains satisfy.
Invertibility of Ideals
Let be a Dedekind domain with field of fractions , and let be any nonzero fractional ideal of . We call invertible if there is a fractional ideal such that . We shall show that all fractional ideals of are invertible.
Given any nonzero fractional ideal of define . is clearly an -module. Moreover, for any nonzero (such an alpha clearly exists, if for then ) we have by the definition of , and so must be a fractional ideal of . It follows that is a fractional ideal of as well, let . By definition, , and so is an integral ideal. We claim that in fact , and so is invertible.
We will need the following lemmas.
Lemma 1: Every nonzero integral ideal of contains a product of prime ideals (counting as the empty product).
Proof: Assume that this is not the case. Let be the collection of integral ideals of not containing a product of prime ideals, so is nonempty and . As is noetherian, must have a maximal element, say . Clearly cannot be prime (otherwise it would contain itself), so there must be with but . But then , and so and contain products of prime ideals. But then also contains a product of prime ideals, contradicting the choice of .
Lemma 2: For any proper integral ideal , there is some $\gamma\in K\sm R$ (Error compiling LaTeX. Unknown error_msg) for which .
Proof: Take any nonzero . By Lemma 1, contains a product of prime ideals, say with minimal (i.e. does not contain a product of prime ideals). As , . As is a proper ideal, it must be contained in some maximal ideal, . Since maximal ideals are prime in commutative rings, is prime. But now . Thus as is prime, for some (if is prime and are ideals with then either or ). But as is a Dedekind domain, must be maximal, so . Now assume WLOG that . By the minimality of , . Take any $b\in P_1\cdots P_{n-1}\sm (a)$ (Error compiling LaTeX. Unknown error_msg) let . We claim that this is the desired .
First if then , a contradiction, so . Now for any , , and so for some . But now , and so , as required.
Now we return to the main proof. Assume that . Then by Lemma 2, there is some $\gamma\in K\sm R$ (Error compiling LaTeX. Unknown error_msg) for which . By the definition of , for any we have and so . It follows that . We claim that this implies (contradicting the choice of ).
Indeed, the map is an -linear map from . As is noetherian, must be a finitely generated -module. Indeed, for some nonzero , must be an integral ideal of , which is finitely generated by the definition of noetherian rings. But if then , so is finitely generated as well. Now take , and let be the matrix representation of with respect to . Then is an matrix with coefficients in and we have: and so is an eigenvalue of . But then is a root of the characteristic polynomial, of . But as has all of its entries in , is a monic polynomial in . Thus as is integrally closed in , .
This is a contradiction, and so we must have , and so is indeed invertible.
In fact, the converse is true as well: if all nonzero ideals are invertible, then is a Dedekind domain. This is sometimes used as a definition of Dedekind domains.