Difference between revisions of "Tower law"
(Statement and proof) |
m |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
− | Given three [[field]]s, <math>F\subseteq K\subseteq L</math> the '''tower law''' states that if <math>[L:K]</math> and <math>[K:F]</math> are both finite then so is <math>[L:F]</math> and | + | Given three [[field]]s, <math>F\subseteq K\subseteq L</math> the '''tower law''' states that if <math>[L:K]</math> and <math>[K:F]</math> are both [[finite]] then so is <math>[L:F]</math> and |
<cmath>[L:F] = [L:K][K:F].</cmath> | <cmath>[L:F] = [L:K][K:F].</cmath> | ||
− | + | Furthermore, if either <math>[L:K]</math> or <math>[K:F]</math> is infinite then so is <math>[L:F]</math>. | |
==Proof== | ==Proof== |
Latest revision as of 07:42, 21 August 2009
Given three fields, the tower law states that if and are both finite then so is and Furthermore, if either or is infinite then so is .
Proof
First consider the case where and are both finite. Let and . Let be a basis for over and be a basis for over . We claim that the set (which clearly has elements) is a basis for over .
First we show that spans . Take any . As is a basis for over , we can write , where . And now as is a basis for over we can write where , for each . So now So indeed spans over .
Now we show that is independent. Assume that there are some such that . So then we have So, as is independent over we get that For all . And hence as is independent over we get for all and . Therefore is indeed independent.
Therefore is indeed a basis, so , as desired.
Now we consider the infinite case. By the above argument if is independent over and is independent over then the set is independent over . Hence if either of and is infinite then there exisit arbitrarily large independent sets in over , so is infinite as well.