Difference between revisions of "Russell's Paradox"

(expand)
(See Also)
 
(3 intermediate revisions by 2 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Russell's Paradox''', creditted to Bertrand Russell, was one of those which forced the axiomatization of set theory.  
+
The '''Russell's Paradox''', credited to Bertrand Russell, was one of those which forced the axiomatization of set theory.  
  
==Paradox==
+
Paradox
We start with the property <math>P</math>: (<math>x</math> does not belong to <math>x</math>). We define <math>C</math> to be the collection of all <math>x</math> with the property <math>P</math>. Now comes the question: does <math>C</math> have the property <math>P</math>? Assuming it does, it cannot be in itself, in spite of satisfying its own membership criterion, a contradiction. Assuming it doesn't, it must be in itself, in spite of not satisfying its own membership criterion. This is the paradox.
+
We start with the property P: (x does not belong to x). We define C to be the collection of all x with the property P. Now comes the question: does C have the property P? Assuming it does, it cannot be in itself, in spite of satisfying its own membership criterion, a contradiction. Assuming it doesn't, it must be in itself, in spite of not satisfying its own membership criterion. This is the paradox.
  
==See Also==
+
See Also
 
*[[Set]]
 
*[[Set]]
  
 
[[Category:Set theory]]
 
[[Category:Set theory]]

Latest revision as of 16:57, 12 May 2023

The Russell's Paradox, credited to Bertrand Russell, was one of those which forced the axiomatization of set theory.

Paradox We start with the property P: (x does not belong to x). We define C to be the collection of all x with the property P. Now comes the question: does C have the property P? Assuming it does, it cannot be in itself, in spite of satisfying its own membership criterion, a contradiction. Assuming it doesn't, it must be in itself, in spite of not satisfying its own membership criterion. This is the paradox.

See Also